The teaching of economics is in crisis.
November 24, 2014
An international student call for pluralism in economics
It is not only the world economy that is in crisis. The teaching of economics is in crisis too, and this crisis has consequences far beyond the university walls. What is taught shapes the minds of the next generation of policymakers, and therefore shapes the societies we live in. We, over 65 associations of economics students from over 30 different countries, believe it is time to reconsider the way economics is taught. We are dissatisfied with the dramatic narrowing of the curriculum that has taken place over the last couple of decades. This lack of intellectual diversity does not only restrain education and research. It limits our ability to contend with the multidimensional challenges of the 21st century – from financial stability, to food security and climate change. The real world should be brought back into the classroom, as well as debate and a pluralism of theories and methods. Such change will help renew the discipline and ultimately create a space in which solutions to society’s problems can be generated.
United across borders, we call for a change of course. We do not claim to have the perfect answer, but we have no doubt that economics students will profit from exposure to different perspectives and ideas. Pluralism will not only help to enrich teaching and research and reinvigorate the discipline. More than this, pluralism carries the promise of bringing economics back into the service of society. Three forms of pluralism must be at the core of curricula: theoretical, methodological and interdisciplinary.
Theoretical pluralism emphasizes the need to broaden the range of schools of thought represented in the curricula. It is not the particulars of any economic tradition we object to. Pluralism is not about choosing sides, but about encouraging intellectually rich debate and learning to critically contrast ideas. Where other disciplines embrace diversity and teach competing theories even when they are mutually incompatible, economics is often presented as a unified body of knowledge. Admittedly, the dominant tradition has internal variations. Yet, it is only one way of doing economics and of looking at the real world. Such uniformity is unheard of in other fields; nobody would take seriously a degree program in psychology that focuses only on Freudianism, or a politics program that focuses only on state socialism. An inclusive and comprehensive economics education should promote balanced exposure to a variety of theoretical perspectives, from the commonly taught neoclassically-based approaches to the largely excluded classical, post-Keynesian, institutional, ecological, feminist, Marxist and Austrian traditions – among others. Most economics students graduate without ever encountering such diverse perspectives in the classroom.
Furthermore, it is essential that core curricula include courses that provide context and foster reflexive thinking about economics and its methods per se, including philosophy of economics and the theory of knowledge. Also, because theories cannot be fully understood independently of the historical context in which they were formulated, students should be systematically exposed to the history of economic thought and to the classical literature on economics as well as to economic history. Currently, such courses are either non-existent or marginalized to the fringes of economics curricula.
Methodological pluralism stresses the need to broaden the range of tools economists employ to grapple with economic questions. It is clear that maths and statistics are crucial to our discipline. But all too often students learn to master quantitative methods without ever discussing if and why they should be used, the choice of assumptions and the applicability of results. Also, there are important aspects of economics which cannot be understood using exclusively quantitative methods: sound economic inquiry requires that quantitative methods are complemented by methods used by other social sciences. For instance, the understanding of institutions and culture could be greatly enhanced if qualitative analysis was given more attention in economics curricula. Nevertheless, most economics students never take a single class in qualitative methods.
Finally, economics education should include interdisciplinary approaches and allow students to engage with other social sciences and the humanities. Economics is a social science; complex economic phenomena can seldom be understood if presented in a vacuum, removed from their sociological, political, and historical contexts. To properly discuss economic policy, students should understand the broader social impacts and moral implications of economic decisions.
While approaches to implementing such forms of pluralism will vary from place to place, general ideas for implementation might include:
- Hiring instructors and researchers who can bring theoretical and methodological diversity to economics programs;
- Creating texts and other pedagogical tools needed to support pluralist course offerings;
- Formalizing collaborations between social sciences and humanities departments or establishing special departments that could oversee interdisciplinary programs blending economics and other fields.
Change will be difficult – it always is. But it is already happening. Indeed, students across the world have already started creating change step by step. We have filled lecture theatres in weekly lectures by invited speakers on topics not included in the curriculum; we have organised reading groups, workshops, conferences; we have analysed current syllabuses and drafted alternative programs; we have started teaching ourselves and others the new courses we would like to be taught. We have founded university groups and built networks both nationally and internationally.
Change must come from many places. So now we invite you – students, economists, and non-economists – to join us and create the critical mass needed for change. See Support us to show your support and connect with our growing networks. Ultimately, pluralism in economics education is essential for healthy public debate. It is a matter of democracy.
Signed, the member organizations of the International Student Initiative for Pluralism in Economics:
- Sociedad de Economía Crítica Argentina y Uruguay, Argentina
- The PPE Society, La Trobe University, Australia
- Society for Pluralist Economics Vienna, Austria
- Nova Ágora, Brazil
- Mouvement étudiant québécois pour un enseignement pluraliste de l’économie, Canada
- Estudios Nueva Economía, Chile
- Grupo de estudiantes y egresados de la Facultad de Economía y Negocios de la Universidad de Chile, Chile
- Det Samfundsøkonomiske Selskab (DSS), Denmark
- Post-Crash Economics Society Essex, England
- Cambridge Society for Economic Pluralism, England
- Better Economics UCLU, England
- Post-Crash Economics Society Manchester, England
- SOAS Open Economics Forum, England
- Alternative Thinking for Economics Society, Sheffield University, England
- LSE Post-Crash Economics England
- Pour un Enseignement Pluraliste de l’Economie dans le Supérieur (PEPS-Economie), France
- Netzwerk Plurale Ökonomik (Network for Pluralist Economics), Germany
- Oikos Köln, Germany
- Real World Economics, Mainz, Germany
- Kritische WissenschaftlerInnen Berlin, Germany
- Arbeitskreis Plurale Ökonomik, München, Germany
- Oikos Leipzig, Germany
- Was ist Ökonomie, Berlin, Germany
- Impuls. für eine neue Wirtschaft, Erfurt, Germany
- Ecoation, Augsburg, Germany
- Kritische Ökonomen, Frankfurt, Germany
- Arbeitskreis Plurale Ökonomik, Hamburg, Germany
- Real World Economics, Heidelberg, Germany
- Stundent HUB Weltethos Institut Tübingen, Germany
- LIE – Lost in Economics e.V., Regensburg, Germany
- Javadhpur University Heterodox Economics Association, India
- Economics Student Forum – Tel Aviv, Israel
- Economics Student Forum – Haifa (Rethinking Economics), Israel
- Rethinking Economics Italia, Italy
- Grupo de Estudiantes por la Enseñanza Plural de la Economía, UNAM, Mexico
- Oeconomicus Economic Club MGIMO, Russia
- Glasgow University Real World Economics Society, Scotland
- Movement for Pluralistic Economics, Slovenia
- Post-Crash Barcelona, Spain
- Asociación de Estudiantes de Económicas de la Universidad Autónoma de Madrid, Spain
- Estudantes de Económicas e Empresariais, Universidade de Santiago de Compostela, Spain
- Lunds Kritiska Ekonomer, Sweden
- Handels Students for Sustainability, Sweden
- PEPS-Helvetia, Switzerland
- Rethinking Economics, UK
- Rethinking Economics New York, United States
- Sociedad de Economia Critica, Argentina and Uruguay
Economics in crisis (2 graphs)
from David Ruccio
Cornelia Strawser, in response to Brad DeLong, notes the importance of the declining labor share in U.S. national income.* She then poses a series of questions that, in her view, should be “raised in the academy and in public discourse”:
– Does the falling labor share arise from rapid technological change?
– Or does it reflect changing power relationships?
– Is it a result of globalization, hence inevitable and irreversible?
– Or is it an anomalous business cycle development that we can expect to fade away?
– What does increasing financialization contribute to the falling labor share?
– Is the labor share made worse by our reliance on monetary stimulus – which encourages more financialization – having failed to deploy a more stimulative fiscal policy?
– If private-sector productivity growth is not raising worker wages, why should workers support it, and should it be a national priority?
– Does the rising capital income share contribute as much to investment demand as the falling labor share subtracts from consumption? Or, since investment demand depends on final consumption demand, does the falling labor share instead cause a vicious downward spiral of self-reinforcing underconsumption and stagnation?
– Is there a case for a compensating structural tax reform that would place a relatively greater burden on capital incomes, and less on labor?
To which one might add an additional question: isn’t it time to reconsider the structure of corporate governance and give employees a role in running the enterprises in which they work?
*There are many different ways of measuring the labor share. In the chart above, I have calculated it in terms of total wage and salary accruals paid to individuals minus employer-paid supplements to wages and salaries, which are best interpreted as deductions from profits that do not go to employees but to others (such as health-insurance companies, retirement accounts, and so forth). Here’s a chart showing total wage and salary accruals with and without the supplements:
Here’s a link to the U.S. Bureau of Economic Analysis’s explanation of how they calculate compensation [pdf].
FROM STTPML ON THE PEDAGOGY OF ECONOMICS AND POLITICAL ECONOMY
social formation mode of production structural marxism
transition to socialist economy bettleheim bettransi
Economic Calculation and Forms of Property Charles Bettleheim
diagrams in economics Pullen65
regression and causality ChenPearl65
Wealth_and_Illfare_CTKurien_2012_ebook
political economy of capitalism 07-037
The Foundations of Capitalist Economy
UnderstandingCapitalismInstructorsManual
world systems wallerstein THYTLK13
rise and future demise of world capitalist economy Wallerstein
capitalist world economy wallerstein 9780521220859ws
Karl Marx´s Grundrisse – Foundations of the critique of political economy 150 years later
terrel-carver-karl-marx-texts-on-method
0521366259.Cambridge.University.Press.The.Cambridge.Companion.to.Marx.Nov.1991
homo economicus and human evolution Mezgebo67
RadicalPoliticalEconomicsOfDFD
Marxism for the few let them eat theory
trading with the enemy higham TWTE_Complete
doug dowd world problems and us power cliffs_edge00-03
capitalism-and-its-economics-a-critical-history-douglas-dowd
Indigenous Epistemology and Scientific Method pdf
From_Political_Economy_to_Freakonomics
Der Anti-Samuelson- Kritik eines repräsentativen Lehrbuchs der bü
mathscience in 21st century Connect_2010_Jan-Feb
old vs new paradigms in economics Fullbrook66
Neoclassical Economics Death of Colander
Neoclassical Economics and Neoliberalism as Neo-Imperialism (2)
InternationalEducationTranslation
eprint of international ed and imper 21598282.2011
Critiques of Steve Keen and NC Economics Chinese version img257
Critiques of Keen and NC Economics English img256
The anti-Samuelson. Volume One. Macroeconomics- basic problems of
The anti-Samuelson. Volume Two. Microeconomics- basic problems of
presentation-at-tsinghua-aug-2012 (1)
Citigroup-Plutonomy-Report-Part-1
Citigroup_Plutonomy_Report_Part_2
citibank plutonomy symposium memo3
Theoretical System of Marx and Engels, completed and proofed.(3) pdf
Marxism and the Transition to Socialism in Latin America
The_Development_of_Modern_Propaganda_in_Britain,_1854-1902_-_FINAL_CORRECTED_THESIS
imperialism brenner-what_is_and_what
BernaysEdward-Propaganda192879P.Scan
David Hawkins – Power Vs Force
5369599-Crystallizing-Public-Opinion-Edward-Bernays
Citibank Plutonomy Report Consolidated
The Ramsey-Keynes dispute
from Lars Syll
Neoclassical economics nowadays usually assumes that agents that have to make choices under conditions of uncertainty behave according to Bayesian rules, axiomatized by Ramsey (1931) and Savage (1954) – that is, they maximize expected utility with respect to some subjective probability measure that is continually updated according to Bayes theorem. If not, they are supposed to be irrational, and ultimately – via some “Dutch book” or “money pump”argument – susceptible to being ruined by some clever “bookie”.
Bayesianism reduces questions of rationality to questions of internal consistency (coherence) of beliefs, but – even granted this questionable reductionism – do rational agents really have to be Bayesian? As I have been arguing elsewhere (e. g. here, here and here) there is no strong warrant for believing so.
In many of the situations that are relevant to economics one could argue that there is simply not enough of adequate and relevant information to ground beliefs of a probabilistic kind, and that in those situations it is not really possible, in any relevant way, to represent an individual’s beliefs in a single probability measure.
Say you have come to learn (based on own experience and tons of data) that the probability of you becoming unemployed in Sweden is 10 %. Having moved to another country (where you have no own experience and no data) you have no information on unemployment and a fortiori nothing to help you construct any probability estimate on. A Bayesian would, however, argue that you would have to assign probabilities to the mutually exclusive alternative outcomes and that these have to add up to 1, if you are rational. That is, in this case – and based on symmetry – a rational individual would have to assign probability 10% to becoming unemployed and 90% of becoming employed.
That feels intuitively wrong though, and I guess most people would agree. Bayesianism cannot distinguish between symmetry-based probabilities from information and symmetry-based probabilities from an absence of information. In these kinds of situations most of us would rather say that it is simply irrational to be a Bayesian and better instead to admit that we “simply do not know” or that we feel ambiguous and undecided. Arbitrary an ungrounded probability claims are more irrational than being undecided in face of genuine uncertainty, so if there is not sufficient information to ground a probability distribution it is better to acknowledge that simpliciter, rather than pretending to possess a certitude that we simply do not possess.
I think this critique of Bayesianism is in accordance with the views of John Maynard Keynes’ A Treatise on Probability (1921) and General Theory (1937). According to Keynes we live in a world permeated by unmeasurable uncertainty – not quantifiable stochastic risk – which often forces us to make decisions based on anything but rational expectations. Sometimes we “simply do not know.” Keynes would not have accepted the view of Bayesian economists, according to whom expectations “tend to be distributed, for the same information set, about the prediction of the theory.” Keynes, rather, thinks that we base our expectations on the confidence or “weight” we put on different events and alternatives. To Keynes expectations are a question of weighing probabilities by “degrees of belief”, beliefs that have preciously little to do with the kind of stochastic probabilistic calculations made by the rational agents modeled by Bayesian economists.
Stressing the importance of Keynes’ view on uncertainty John Kay writes in Financial Times:
Keynes believed that the financial and business environment was characterised by “radical uncertainty”. The only reasonable response to the question “what will interest rates be in 20 years’ time?” is “we simply do not know” …
For Keynes, probability was about believability, not frequency. He denied that our thinking could be described by a probability distribution over all possible future events, a statistical distribution that could be teased out by shrewd questioning – or discovered by presenting a menu of trading opportunities. In the 1920s he became engaged in an intellectual battle on this issue, in which the leading protagonists on one side were Keynes and the Chicago economist Frank Knight, opposed by a Cambridge philosopher, Frank Ramsey, and later by Jimmie Savage, another Chicagoan.
Keynes and Knight lost that debate, and Ramsey and Savage won, and the probabilistic approach has maintained academic primacy ever since. A principal reason was Ramsey’s demonstration that anyone who did not follow his precepts – anyone who did not act on the basis of a subjective assessment of probabilities of future events – would be “Dutch booked” … A Dutch book is a set of choices such that a seemingly attractive selection from it is certain to lose money for the person who makes the selection.
I used to tell students who queried the premise of “rational” behaviour in financial markets – where rational means are based on Bayesian subjective probabilities – that people had to behave in this way because if they did not, people would devise schemes that made money at their expense. I now believe that observation is correct but does not have the implication I sought. People do not behave in line with this theory, with the result that others in financial markets do devise schemes that make money at their expense.
Although this on the whole gives a succinct and correct picture of Keynes’s view on probability, I think it’s necessary to somewhat qualify in what way and to what extent Keynes “lost” the debate with the Bayesians Frank Ramsey and Jim Savage.
In economics it’s an indubitable fact that few mainstream neoclassical economists work within the Keynesian paradigm. All more or less subscribe to some variant of Bayesianism. And some even say that Keynes acknowledged he was wrong when presented with Ramsey’s theory. This is a view that has unfortunately also been promulgated by Robert Skidelsky in his otherwise masterly biography of Keynes. But I think it’s fundamentally wrong. Let me elaborate on this point (the argumentation is more fully presented in my book John Maynard Keynes (SNS, 2007)).
It’s a debated issue in newer research on Keynes if he, as some researchers maintain, fundamentally changed his view on probability after the critique levelled against his A Treatise on Probability by Frank Ramsey. It has been exceedingly difficult to present evidence for this being the case.
Ramsey’s critique was mainly that the kind of probability relations that Keynes was speaking of in Treatise actually didn’t exist and that Ramsey’s own procedure (betting) made it much easier to find out the “degrees of belief” people were having. I question this both from a descriptive and a normative point of view.
What Keynes is saying in his response to Ramsey is only that Ramsey “is right” in that people’s “degrees of belief” basically emanates in human nature rather than in formal logic.
Patrick Maher, former professor of philosophy at the University of Illinois, even suggests that Ramsey’s critique of Keynes’s probability theory in some regards is invalid:
Keynes’s book was sharply criticized by Ramsey. In a passage that continues to be quoted approvingly, Ramsey wrote:
“But let us now return to a more fundamental criticism of Mr. Keynes’ views, which is the obvious one that there really do not seem to be any such things as the probability relations he describes. He supposes that, at any rate in certain cases, they can be perceived; but speaking for myself I feel confident that this is not true. I do not perceive them, and if I am to be persuaded that they exist it must be by argument; moreover, I shrewdly suspect that others do not perceive them either, because they are able to come to so very little agreement as to which of them relates any two given propositions.” (Ramsey 1926, 161)
I agree with Keynes that inductive probabilities exist and we sometimes know their values. The passage I have just quoted from Ramsey suggests the following argument against the existence of inductive probabilities. (Here P is a premise and C is the conclusion.)
P: People are able to come to very little agreement about inductive proba- bilities.
C: Inductive probabilities do not exist.P is vague (what counts as “very little agreement”?) but its truth is still questionable. Ramsey himself acknowledged that “about some particular cases there is agreement” (28) … In any case, whether complicated or not, there is more agreement about inductive probabilities than P suggests.
Ramsey continued:
“If … we take the simplest possible pairs of propositions such as “This is red” and “That is blue” or “This is red” and “That is red,” whose logical relations should surely be easiest to see, no one, I think, pretends to be sure what is the probability relation which connects them.” (162)
I agree that nobody would pretend to be sure of a numeric value for these probabilities, but there are inequalities that most people on reflection would agree with. For example, the probability of “This is red” given “That is red” is greater than the probability of “This is red” given “That is blue.” This illustrates the point that inductive probabilities often lack numeric values. It doesn’t show disagreement; it rather shows agreement, since nobody pretends to know numeric values here and practically everyone will agree on the inequalities.
Ramsey continued:
“Or, perhaps, they may claim to see the relation but they will not be able to say anything about it with certainty, to state if it ismore or less than 1/3, or so on. They may, of course, say that it is incomparable with any numerical relation, but a relation about which so little can be truly said will be of little scientific use and it will be hard to convince a sceptic of its existence.” (162)
Although the probabilities that Ramsey is discussing lack numeric values, they are not “incomparable with any numerical relation.” Since there are more than three different colors, the a priori probability of “This is red” must be less than 1/3 and so its probability given “This is blue” must likewise be less than 1/3. In any case, the “scientific use” of something is not relevant to whether it exists. And the question is not whether it is “hard to convince a sceptic of its existence” but whether the sceptic has any good argument to support his position …
Ramsey concluded the paragraph I have been quoting as follows:
“Besides this view is really rather paradoxical; for any believer in induction must admit that between “This is red” as conclusion and “This is round” together with a billion propositions of the form “a is round and red” as evidence, there is a finite probability relation; and it is hard to suppose that as we accumulate instances there is suddenly a point, say after 233 instances, at which the probability relation becomes finite and so comparable with some numerical relations.” (162)
Ramsey is here attacking the view that the probability of “This is red” given “This is round” cannot be compared with any number, but Keynes didn’t say that and it isn’t my view either. The probability of “This is red” given only “This is round” is the same as the a priori probability of “This is red” and hence less than 1/3. Given the additional billion propositions that Ramsey mentions, the probability of “This is red” is high (greater than 1/2, for example) but it still lacks a precise numeric value. Thus the probability is always both comparable with some numbers and lacking a precise numeric value; there is no paradox here.
I have been evaluating Ramsey’s apparent argument from P to C. So far I have been arguing that P is false and responding to Ramsey’s objections to unmeasurable probabilities. Now I want to note that the argument is also invalid. Even if P were true, it could be that inductive probabilities exist in the (few) cases that people generally agree about. It could also be that the disagreement is due to some people misapplying the concept of inductive probability in cases where inductive probabilities do exist. Hence it is possible for P to be true and C false …
I conclude that Ramsey gave no good reason to doubt that inductive probabilities exist.
Ramsey’s critique made Keynes more strongly emphasize the individuals’ own views as the basis for probability calculations, and less stress that their beliefs were rational. But Keynes’s theory doesn’t stand or fall with his view on the basis for our “degrees of belief” as logical. The core of his theory – when and how we are able to measure and compare different probabilities – he doesn’t change. Unlike Ramsey he wasn’t at all sure that probabilities always were one-dimensional, measurable, quantifiable or even comparable entities.
Superior Economists
from Peter Radford
Actually the paper I just read is called “The Superiority of Economists”. It’s another analysis of thee economics profession by Marion Fourcade, this time in association with Etienne Ollion and Yann Algan. It is well worth reading and fits neatly in the same analytical tradition as Fourcade’s 2009 book “Economists and Societies”.
The problem is that none of it is particularly surprising. The point being that economists, by asserting their superiority vis other social sciences have exposed themselves to greater scrutiny and criticism than their peers. This has, apparently, induced more soul-searching within economics than in those other social sciences. Along with the air of superiority that economists exude due to their self-proclaimed intellectualism, comes a big dollop of insecurity.
Which is a point worth making: economists, for all their arrogant assertion of the truths of their ‘science’, are a little insecure about something. Hence, perhaps, their brashness and lack of interaction with their peers. One of Fourcade’s findings is that economists are more isolated as a profession than those around them. They quote fewer non-economics papers and books in their own work, and are almost haughty in the disregard of insights that other social sciences take very seriously.
Which we all know.
Another point worth drawing attention to in the paper is the impact of finance and business schools. Plenty of us have discussed the emergence of the pseudo science that is modern finance, and its constant reciprocity with neoclassical economics. They are both based on absurd assumptions about human behavior, yet because of their insular character are almost immune to empirical attack. On the contrary, as Fourcade et al spell out, finance in particular has been a performative activity over the last thirty years as it attempts to bend the real world to approximate the theoretical, rather than trying to reflect or explain that real world. A torrent of so-called financial innovations are the end result of this performativity. We know how stable they all turned out to be.
Now here’s my nit-picking with the paper.
Buried right at the end, in the concluding paragraph, is this statement:
“Most modern economists have a strong practical bent. They believe in the ideal of an expert-advised democracy, in which their competence would be utilized and on display in high profile, non-elective positions in government and other institutions.”
I don’t agree. Economists don’t want an “expert led democracy” at all. They want a society led by Platonic philosopher kings, with economists being those very folk. Economists, those on the right anyway, don’t have time for democracy.
As you know, I have been on quite a kick lately [here, here, here, and here] criticizing mainstream economics as being fundamentally anti-democratic. I base this assertion on the utopian thrust in economics to describe an apolitical method of resource distribution – one in which politics, as expressed through government action, can only make things worse. As I see it the centrality of markets in economic theorizing is an attempt to eliminate politics. And, since the emergence of democracy as our standard way of expressing politics institutionally, this implies at least a disdain for said democracy, if not an outright contempt.
Of course I realize that other economists, good for them, openly acknowledge the many flaws in real world markets. Indeed, so many such flaws have now been identified that we might reasonably ask which is the exception: the flawed market or the supposed flawless version? My money would be on the flawed one, but that’s for elsewhere.
The problem is that, as recently evidenced in Deirdre McCloskey’s critique of Piketty, hard core right of center economists just can’t let go of the flawless market version their beloved theory describes. Such flawlessness is not the result of some deep analysis, but is, in truth, the desired end point established a priori by their ideological bent. A bent that desperately needs the result of their theorizing to result in the establishment of perfection in markets and nothing but imperfection in governments.
Which is to say that such economists want to preclude the possibility that democratically elected government could possibly dabble around in the economy to good effect. This is an expression of simultaneous distrust of democracy and idolization of markets. It can be thought of no other way.
But that’s just me griping again. I appreciate Fourcade’s continued forays into the sociology of the economics profession. They help me understand the extent of the isolation the profession wallows in, and how far we have to go before the collective social sciences offer us a deep and holistic look into civil society. Unfortunately economics is holding us back at present. I wish that were not the case.